Quine was famously skeptical about facts. As I
said in the last post, Quine can be seen as resolutely maintaining something
which Strawson seems to suggest at his most objectionable moments. This will enable us to give a sharp
diagnosis of one particular skeptical confusion about facts.
What
on the part of true sentences is meant to correspond to
what on the part of reality? If we seek a correspondence word by
word, we find ourselves eking reality out with a complement of
abstract objects fabricated for the sake of the correspondence. Or
perhaps we settle for a correspondence of whole sentences with facts:
a sentence is true if it reports a fact. But here again we have
fabricated substance for an empty doctrine. The world is full of
things, variously related, but what, in addition to all that, are
facts? They are projected from true sentences for the sake of
correspondence.
But let us ponder
this last maneuver for a moment. The truth of 'Snow is white' is due,
we are told, to the fact that snow is white. The true sentence 'Snow
is white' corresponds to the fact that snow is white. The sentence
'Snow is white' is true if and only if it is a fact that snow is
white. Now we have worked the fact, factitious fiction that it is,
into a corner where we can deal it the coup de grace. The combination
'it is a fact that' is vacuous and can be dropped; 'It is a fact that
snow is white' reduces to 'Snow is white'. Our account of the truth
of 'Snow is white' in terms of facts has now come down to this: 'Snow
is white' is true if and only if snow is white.
This
nicely illustrates the attitude about fact-talk we were
arguing Strawson had, and which Quine shares. All but the thinnest,
most eliminable uses of fact-talk, such as prefacing propositions
with 'It is a fact that', are cast out as bad philosophy. But this
doesn't at all follow from the explanatory failure, if such there be,
of attempting to account for truth in terms of correspondence with
facts; why would dubious theories of truth be the only other thing
you can do with fact talk, besides these most eliminable uses? We
haven't been given a shred of evidence to suggest that they are.
Consider
the argument in the second paragraph. It can be resisted from the
point of view of the correspondence theory. Furthermore, we can put
the correspondence theory to one side and show that, in any case, it
does not even begin to show facts to be 'fictions'.
First
of all, consider the point of view of a fact-based correspondence
theory: the truth of propositions can be explained in terms of a
relation of correspondence and certain relata, facts. Quine's
transformation, which he just blandly performs without a word of
explanation or justification, of the 'corresponds to the fact that'
formulation into the 'if and only if it is a fact that' formulation,
from this point of view, could justly be said to rather obscure the
explanation. And the next step, of declaring 'it is a fact that' to
be vacuous and dropping it, is completely indefensible. One thing is
the fact that you can drop that phrase in many ordinary contexts –
it does not at all follow that you can further mutilate the
philosophical explanation in question in the same way.
In
Strawson's case, the “elimination” was of a different sort,
effected by imagining a counterfactual scenario in which we speak a
language consisting only of simple commands. In the present case, the "elimination" is effected by transforming sentences of our language
so that reference to facts disappears. It fails triply:
Firstly,
the transformations are unjustified from the point of view of the
correspondence theory.
Secondly:
no evidence has been given that there are not other occurrences of
fact talk which Quine cannot eliminate.
Thirdly:
even if fact-talk were always eliminable, that doesn't eliminate
facts, doesn't show them not to exist – that would be a use-mention
confusion. (This point was made by my former teacher Adrian
Heathcote.)
(Quine,
or a good Quinean, however, may object that this third objection
misses the point, and that there is something lying behind this
argument: Quine's conception of ontology. I will not get into that
possibility here.)
These three problems
with Quine's “elimination” aside, we still have the contention in
the first paragraph that facts are 'projected from true sentences'.
This suggestive idea, particularly in light of our considerations
about the role of concepts (or internal meanings, or modes of
presentation) in the individuation of facts, could give independent
support to the idea that facts are fiction, so it requires
separate treatment. To this end, we shall now consider the idea of a
projective fallacy in general, and go on to show that it is Quine,
not the person who speaks of facts, who is guilty of one here.
Projective
Fallacies (or Confusions) in General
There is a general
idea, which seems to me to be important and useful in philosophy,
that we sometimes get led into error or confusion by reading features
of our language or thought into the world – or alternatively,
projecting them onto the world.
Before considering
some (hopefully relatively uncontentious) examples of such confusions
or errors, let us review some classic philosophical expressions of
the general idea.
Hume,
in A Treatise of Human
Nature: “The
mind has a great propensity to spread itself on objects.” [Book 1,
Part 3, §XIV]
Russell,
in his Logical Atomism lectures: 'There
is a good deal of importance to philosophy in the theory of
symbolism, a good deal more than one time I thought. I think the
importance is almost entirely negative, i.e., the importance lies in
the fact that unless you are fairly self-conscious about symbols,
unless you are fairly aware of the relation of the symbol to what it
symbolizes, you will find yourself attributing to the thing
properties which only belong to the symbol. That, of course, is
especially likely in very abstract studies such as philosophical
logic, because the subject-matter that you are supposed to be
thinking of is so exceedingly difficult and elusive that any person
who has ever tried to think about it knows you do not think about it
except perhaps once in six months for half a minute.'
Wittgenstein,
in the Investigations
104: 'We predicate of
the thing what lies in the method of representing it.'
I
will speak of 'projective fallacies' to refer to instances of this
sort of thing, with the caveat that 'confusion' may be more
appropriate in many cases, since there need not be any definite
fallacious inference
drawn, in the sense of a
transition from proposition to proposition forming part of a chain of
reasoning.
Examples
of Projective Fallacies
Here I will try to
give some examples of projective fallacies which aren't very
philosophically loaded, in order to give a better idea of what they
are.
Bands in the
rainbow: looking at rainbows in relative scientific ignorance, it
would be natural to think that the bands of colour we perceive in
them correspond to intrinsic structural features of them. We might
expect that bits of the rainbow near the end (width-wise) of band are
more intrinsically different from those near the same blurry boundary
on the other side, than are two equally distant bits which fall
within one band. But this would be a projective fallacy.
Illusory failures
of homophony: Taking two words with the same pronunciation but
different spellings in isolation, and saying them one after the other
by themselves, we might persuade ourselves that we ordinarily
pronounce them very slightly differently, when this is not in fact
the case. A difference which lies only in our mode of representing
speech has been projected into our speech.
Taking
an “operator” for a representative:
An extra-terrestrial who had correctly concluded that road signs
sometimes depict objects to be found in their vicinity (such as
speed-bump signs, signs indicating the presence of wildlife, etc.),
might see a sign disallowing dogs and mistakenly infer that there are
creatures nearby with large crosses attached to their bodies.
Incidental
features of models: A boy makes
a model of a boat he admires, and uses a piece of wood in which he
had made, at another time and for some other purpose, a regular
series of indentations. Years later, as a grown man, he finds the
model he made, notices and remembers deliberately making the
indentations, and forms the erroneous idea that the boat he admired
bore indentations in the corresponding place.
Projection-Based
Skepticism about Facts
Let us return now to
Quine's formulation of projection-based skepticism about facts. He
said:
The world is full of
things, variously related, but what, in addition to all that, are
facts? They are projected from true sentences for the sake of
correspondence.
In other words, the
idea that there are facts involves a projective fallacy. In the
following two sections I want to show that this is completely wrong,
and ironically so: it is Quine who is guilty of a projective fallacy
here, in thinking that the believer of facts is guilty of a
projective fallacy.
Something
Which Is True:
A Genetic Point about Ideas of Facts
We
talk of particular facts – we have concepts, or ideas, of
particular facts. How do we arrive at these? I think it is plausible
to say that we derive them, in some sense, from true propositions.
Think of how we form our ideas of particular propositions: first we
formulate the propositions, then we produce an idea of that
proposition. We might say these ideas of propositions are projected
from the propositions themselves. Likewise with ideas of facts, although the
projection is different.
This
may be called a genetic point about ideas of particular facts, since
it is not a piece of semantics or analysis, but rather a hypothesis
about how certain cognitive structures come about.
It
seems plausible, does it not, that in order to have an idea of a
particular fact, you need to have some true propositions under your
belt? The reason for this, we may say, is that our ideas of
particular facts are – in some, if not all cases – derived from
our representations that such-and-such is the case, when it is the
case – that is, from true propositions.
The
Irony of Projection-Based Skepticism About Facts
We
are now in a position to see that Quine, in painting the idea that
there are facts as guilty of a projective fallacy, is himself guilty
of a projective fallacy: he has projected a property of our ideas
of facts – namely, their being derived, or projected, from our true
propositions – onto facts themselves, and concluded that, since
facts are also meant to be mind- and language-independent, the
whole idea of facts is bankrupt; facts are impossible fictions. But that is a mistake.
Reference
Quine, W. V. (1987). Quiddities: An Intermittently Philosophical Dictionary. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.