This post is an attempt at stating and evaluating an approach to analyzing the concept of apriority as it applies to propositions.
Follow-up: An Account of the Analytic/Synthetic Distinction
Follow-up: An Account of the Analytic/Synthetic Distinction
My conception of propositions, which sees them as having an internal nature
constituted by their place in the system of language and thought to
which they belong, but sometimes also external projective relations
to the world, is highly suggestive of an approach to analysing the a
priori-a posteriori
distinction.
Using
'a priori' in such a
way as not to imply truth, so that a proposition can be a
priori true or a
priori false, we might give
expression to the basic idea by saying:
A
proposition is a priori
iff either truth or falsity is an internal property of it.
Or,
using 'a priori' like
'necessary', in such a way as to imply truth (that is, meaning what
'true a priori' means
on the above usage):
A
proposition is a priori
iff truth is an internal property of it.
(We will stick to
the first usage.)
An
account of this sort is attractive from my point of view for two
related reasons. Firstly, it explains the feeling that definitions or
accounts of the a priori which
involve considerations of a knowing subject, and what such a subject
can (in some sense) do without need (in some sense) of experience (in
some sense), fail to get at the heart of the matter. That is, the
feeling that a proposition's being a priori
or a posteriori is a
matter of the nature of the proposition itself, and that the stuff
about being able to know an a priori
proposition independent of experience (in some elusive sense) holds
as a consequence of
that proposition's being a priori,
rather than constituting that property.
Secondly,
many philosophers are skeptical of the notion of the a
priori, or of the idea that
anything genuinely falls under it. But topics at the centre of the
present work, such as the existence of the necessary a
posteriori and the contingent a
priori, involve a notion of the
a priori, and
furthermore, one which is held not to be vacuous. If I can provide a
new account of the notion I intend here, perhaps these skeptics will
be able to enter into my discussion further than they would be able
or willing to otherwise.
On
this account, the concepts 'a priori'
and 'a posteriori' are
broadly logical. They can also be called epistemological if one
wishes, but there is a danger in that, since by itself it leaves one
free to overlook the distinction between properties like that of
being a priori, which
have to do with the nature of the propositions which possess them,
and blatantly epistemological properties like that of being known,
that of being hard to understand, that of being easy to verify, etc.,
the very constitution of which involves relationships to knowers.
That
said, it is of course open to anyone to stipulate that 'a
priori' is to have a meaning
given in terms of a knowing subject and what they can do. But I would
think of the word in that usage as expressing a property the
possession of which is explained by possession of the property
expressed by the word as I use it - a broadly logical property. I use
'a priori' that way
because I find this latter to be of more fundamental interest, but
I'm not concerned to insist on or argue for such a usage. The point
about a broadly logical property explaining, or having as a
consequence, stuff about what a knowing subject can do is supposed to
help motivate the
notion or notions I want to propose, but even that is secondary.
My primary concern is just to propose them and try to make them clear
What
do I mean by saying that a priori
propositions' truth-values are internal to them? I do not mean that a
priori propositions –
individuated the way we are individuating propositions here, such
that external projective relations are held fixed – necessarily
have the truth-values they have. (In that case, it would be difficult
or impossible to allow the class of a priori
truths to differ from the class of necessary truths.)
The
thought is, rather: with many propositions, their internal meanings –
that is, their positions in the language-system to which they belong
– do not by themselves determine a truth-value; rather, this
depends on their external connections to reality, and what lies on
the reality end of the connections. But with the a priori
propositions, there is no such dependence; internal meaning
determines truth-value. Or we might use the pair of locutions 'in
virtue of' and 'irrespective of': a
posteriori
propositions have the truth-values they have partly in virtue of what
(if anything) lies on the reality end of external projective
relations borne by them, whereas a priori propositions
have the truth-values they have irrespective of that. We might even
simply say that their internal meanings, in contrast to a
posteriori propositions, have
truth-values already, all by
themselves.
Is Our Notion of A Priority
Explicable in Terms of Twin-Earthability?
I think this idea, as explained in various ways above, and guided by our pre-existing, traditional conception of a priority, can have considerable philosophical value. It will turn out to be worthwhile, however, to see what happens if we try to explicate this notion of internality of truth-value by means of the concept of Twin Earthability. We may say:
A proposition is
Twin Earthable iff in some possible situation, a proposition with the
same internal meaning has a different truth-value.
And then:
A proposition is a
priori iff it has its truth-value internally iff it is not Twin
Earthable.
This seems a
natural strategy, since if a proposition has its truth-value
irrespective of its external connections to reality, then Twin
Earthing it shouldn't be able to change that. And that is correct,
but for the strategy to succeed, we also need it to be the case that
Twin Earthing is unable to change a proposition's truth-value only
if it has this truth-value irrespective of its external
connections to reality. And certain kinds of propositions might seem
like counterexamples to this, such as 'I exist', 'Language exists'
(where 'language' means concrete linguistic phenomena) and 'I am
uttering a sentence now' (where 'uttering' is taken to mean a
spatiotemporal process).
I am indebted to
discussions of Chalmers ('The Foundations of Two-Dimensional
Semantics', 'Epistemic Two-Dimensional Semantics') for these
examples, and for the notion of Twin Earthability (although he
defines it over sentence-tokens), which Chalmers derived in turn from
Putnam's famous Twin Earth thought experiment.
In
Chalmers' discussion, the examples are given as counterexamples to a
different sort of account of a priority, and for different reasons.
Chalmers' target is a particular class of interpretations of what he
calls 'The Core Thesis': 'For any sentence S, S is a priori
iff S has a necessary 1-intension'. Namely, those interpretations on
which intensions are regarded are 'any sort of linguistic or semantic
contextual intensions'. (Chalmers goes on to argue for what he calls
'epistemic intensions'.) Chalmers is testing this account against a
notion of a priority understood along traditional lines, in terms of
knowledge and experience. We, on the other hand, are, at least in the
first instance, testing non-Twin-Earthability against our notion of a
priority as internality of truth-value. (We will eventually come back
and consider how these two notions - non-Twin-Earthability and
internality – might line up with a more traditional notion
involving knowledge and experience.)
First, it might
seem that 'Language exists' and 'I am uttering now', construed the
way they are supposed to be construed, namely as implying certain
spatiotemporal goings-on, do not carry their truth-values inside
themselves. It might seem like they must reach out and get their
truth from those spatiotemporal goings-on.
They have
non-Twin-Earthability, not because they are true irrespective of what
lies on the reality end of their external projective relations to
reality (that isn't the case), but rather because any Twin-Earthing
of them, any proposition with the same internal meaning, is sure to
bear external projective relations to reality such that what lies on
the reality end of these relations makes the proposition true. (They
are non-Twin-Earthable for what we might call transcendental reasons:
their instantiation guarantees their truth; their truth conditions
are subsumed under their instantiation-conditions.)
Regarding 'I
exist', we might think: this cannot be true in virtue of internal
meaning, since what makes it true is that I actually exist –
this proposition reaches out to me.
There are numerous
unclear and discomforting things about all this, however, especially
the 'I exist' case. (If we imagine 'I exist' reaching out to us,
aren't we thinking of our bodies? And isn't there a way of construing
'I'-propositions such that they don't imply the existence of
bodies?). We will try to address them below.
(To anticipate,
since this may ease comprehension: I will end up going along with the
train of thought above regarding 'Language exists' and 'I am uttering
now', but rejecting it for 'I exist', provided 'I' is construed so as
not to imply the existence of a body. These are very confusing
topics, however, and I don't wish to be dogmatic.)
On the Peculiarity of these
Examples
First, a word about
the peculiarity – the weird basicness, so to speak – of these
examples.
Throughout my investigation of the
difficulties arising with these examples, I have been heartened but
also troubled by how peculiar they are – all of them, but
especially 'I exist'.
Heartened, because
since this proposition ('I exist') is so peculiar, the fact that it
raises confusing problems in connection with our analysis of a
priority should worry us less than if a less peculiar, more worldly
sort of example raised these problems. The confusing problems
presumably have a lot to do with the peculiarity of 'I exist', and we
know that “the first person” raises confusing problems anyway.
It might even look
like this is a peculiarly philosophical proposition, what
Wittgenstein might have called a pseudo-proposition, especially when
we reflect that it may not even concern a body.
But –
and this is why it is troubling – that wouldn't absolve us in any
clear way of the need to square our account of a priority with it –
it is one thing to be dismissive of certain propositions when you
aren't putting forward an account of a general notion in
propositional typology, but I am
doing that: I'm saying that a proposition (any proposition) is a
priori if it has its truth-value
internally.
That
leaves the option of arguing that 'I exist' is no proposition at all,
but that's not an inviting prospect. It seems dogmatic and ad
hoc.
Secondly,
and connected with this last point: it isn't clear that 'I exist'
really is a peculiarly
philosophical proposition with no practical use. Couldn't people
(indeed, don't they sometimes?) assert 'I exist' in order to make
someone more mindful and just toward them? And couldn't someone whose
existence is in doubt, but whose supposed appearance is well-known,
appear to the doubters and say 'I exist'? (Furthermore, aren't these
instances of the very same (internal) proposition-meaning as
Descartes tried to establish with the cogito? And that's not to say
that weird, peculiarly philosophical things weren't happening there.
Clearly they were.)
Accordingly, I will
face up to these difficulties as best I can. I will now discuss 'I
exist' and argue that it can be maintained to have its truth-value
internally, when 'I' is construed so as not to imply the existence of
a body. Following that, I will consider the other examples, 'Language
exists' and 'I am uttering now'. (These also seem peculiar, and this
seems to have to do with their being good candidate instances of
Wittgenstein's remark in On Certainty (#83): The truth of
certain empirical propositions belongs to our frame of reference. We
will discuss this in turn.)
'I Exist'
Here is one consideration which throws
doubt on the idea that 'I exist' doesn't have its truth-value
internally, since it must reach out to me – i.e. a consideration
which suggests that perhaps it does
have its truth-value internally after all.
Suppose a computer system used by an
administrator allows them to enter queries such as 'user23 space?',
and the computer will tell them how much disk space user23 has left.
The administrator's username is 'admin', so they can find out how
much disk space they have left with 'admin space?'. But to save
inputting time, a first-personal pronoun is introduced, so that the
administrator and other users can enter 'I' place of their username
in such queries. Let us suppose that a command involving 'I' is,
under the hood, first transformed so that its occurrences of 'I' are
replaced with the username of whoever is logged in (this username, we
may suppose, is sitting in a particular memory location, ready for
this purpose), and then passed on to be executed.
Now suppose there is a query
'loggedin?', so that the administrator can find out if user23 is
logged in with 'user23 loggedin?'. When the administrator enters 'I
loggedin?', the computer first looks up the username of the current
user where it waits in memory (in this case 'admin'), plugs that in
in place of 'I', and sends that to be executed. Suppose the system
now searches a constantly updated list for the name 'admin', and
returns 'Yes' if it reaches that name, 'No' if it reaches the end
without finding it.
There is an obvious inefficiency here.
Pointless as the 'I loggedin?' query might be in practise, if for
some reason it had to be executed a trillion trillion times (say, at
the whim of a rich eccentric, or for an art project), it might be
worth modifying the software so that queries containing 'I' are first
checked for 'loggedin?', in which case 'Yes' is immediately returned.
And note that we don't need to first study the results of 'I
loggedin?' working in this inefficient way – don't need to study
what's on the dynamic list of users – in order to see this. We look
into the system and see that it can only go one way.
It seems to me that if we think of an
instance of 'I exist' as functioning like 'I loggedin?' in the
unmodified computer system, we may be
inclined to think that its truth-value is not internal to it,
but if we think of it as functioning more like 'I loggedin?' in the
modified system, we will judge that its truth-value is internal to
it. On that way of thinking of it, we might say there is a tight
conceptual connection, an empirically indefeasible connection,
between 'I' and 'exist'. (More on conceptual connections in a future post.)
But what about the first option:
thinking of 'I exist' as functioning like 'I loggedin?' in the first
system? What might this come to? Well, the truly analogous procedure
would be something like: when I ask myself whether I exist, I take
'I' as an abbreviation for my name, and then accordingly ask myself
'Does TH exist?', and then I use the same method I use when I
consider whether someone else exists – perhaps trying to observe my
body, or traces of my activity. That is plainly not how it works. But
perhaps there is a half-way reasonable sort of procedure we can
imagine, which contrasts with the immediate verification of 'I exist'
based on a tight conceptual connection. Descartes' procedure comes to
mind: I must exist, since I would have to exist in order to be
thinking about whether I exist. (Perhaps there is a tight connection
between 'I' and 'think.)
But this is not an empirical procedure,
and it doesn't involve looking out into the world. This suggests that
'I exist', despite what we might have been inclined to say (perhaps
on the basis of thinking of 'I' as requiring a body), can be
maintained to have its truth-value internally, and so be a priori
according to the account proposed.
Here I am using
notions like 'empirical procedure', and so making appealing to
elements of the more traditional, pre-existing conception of a
priority. This would be fishy if I were trying to fully explain those
existing conceptions by means of other, independently understandable
conceptions. But that's not how I think of it: traditional
conceptions of a priority help explain internality of truth-value as
well as vice versa. To anticipate: we will end up with two
mutually supporting conceptions, giving us two angles on a single
important division in propositional typology.
'Language Exists' and 'I am
Uttering Now'
What about
'Language exists' and 'I am uttering now'?
Remember, it is
stipulated that 'language' and 'uttering' here mean physical,
spatiotemporal phenomena.
It seems to me
that, so interpreted, these cases clearly do not have their
truth-values internally. They do reach out and get their
truth, not just their meaning, from outside language – that train
of thought is one I want to go along with. (Its not applying, despite
possible appearances, to 'I exist', turns on the fact that 'I exist'
as construed does not imply the existence of a body.)
There are, however,
superficial appearances to the contrary. When we ask ourselves 'Does
language exist?' and 'Am I uttering now?', we don't actually
do any “looking out into the world”, as I have, speaking
figuratively, said these propositions themselves do. It seems that we
just immediately, or after a moment's reflection, see that the answer
is 'Yes' in both cases. Just like with 'Do I exist?'.
And yet I am
insisting that there is a fundamental difference of category here. I
think we can get clearer here by considering further the category
that 'Language exists' and 'I am uttering now' belong to –
considering, that is, what is characteristic of them as opposed to
the propositions I want to call a priori?
I think this was one
of the main topics, if not the main topic, of Wittgenstein's last
work On Certainty. Wittgenstein was responding to Moore's work
in epistemology – his 'Defence of Common Sense', wherein he claims
to know he has a hand. Apparently Normal Malcolm had some role
turning Wittgenstein's attention to this late in the latter's life.
The following
remarks seem to characterise the peculiar class to which 'Language
exists' etc. belong (I will them the 'Moorean' propositions):
83.
The truth of certain empirical propositions belongs to our frame of
reference.
136.
When Moore says he knows such and such, he is really enumerating a
lot of empirical propositions which we affirm without special
testing; propositions, that is, which have a peculiar logical role in
the system of our empirical propositions.
137.
... Moore's assurance that he knows... does not interest us. The
propositions, however, which Moore retails as examples of such known
truths are indeed interesting. Not because anyone knows their truth,
or believes he knows them, but because they all have a similar role
in the system of our empirical judgments.
138. We don't, for example, arrive at any of them as a result of investigation. …
138. We don't, for example, arrive at any of them as a result of investigation. …
Note that these
Moorean propositions won't generally be non-Twin-Earthable, like
'Language exists' and 'I am uttering now' (which are clearly special
in that their truth is guaranteed transcendentally, i.e. by the
preconditions of formulating them). It is the combination of
non-Twin-Earthability and Mooreanness which makes these cases, and
their nature, require special consideration from the point of view of
our account of a priority as internality of truth-value.
Wittgenstein calls
the peculiar role of Moorean propositions a 'logical' role, and it is
not hard to see why: that we have empirical propositions playing this
role, i.e. being part of the framework which guides thought and
enquiry, is part of how our practise of thought and inquiry works.
But a proposition's
playing this role is not an immutable or intrinsic fact about that
proposition, and that is the very thing – I want to say – which
makes Moorean propositions empirical rather than a priori.
Here is a metaphor
I find helpful: imagine a cluster of metal frames, some of which have
two feet (I will call them 'biframes'), others of which have three
('triframes'). The biframes need support in order to stand – they
are built to be able to stand or fall. The triframes can stand by
themselves. At the periphery of the cluster there are both biframes
and triframes, and some of the biframes are held up by bits of wood.
No biframe could be supported by wood alone; but some are held up by
frames and wood, others by frames alone (which may themselves be held
up by wood, or by further frames held up by wood, etc.). Any biframe,
if you rearranged the cluster sufficiently and removed certain bits
of wood, would fall, but some may be very hard or impossible to get
at. (On Certainty #255: 'What I hold fast to is not one
proposition but a nest of propositions'.)
Frames correspond
to propositions. Their standing corresponds to truth or belief. Wood
corresponds to experience, empirical confirmation. Triframes
correspond to a priori propositions, biframes to empirical
propositions.
The biframes which
stand without being in contact with wood, i.e. which are supported by
other frames, correspond roughly to Moorean propositions: the special
category of empirical propositions with which we are concerned, and
with which Moore and Wittgenstein were concerned. Or perhaps better:
out of these standing biframes not in direct contact with
wood, some are more robust than others with respect to the removal of
bits of wood. Some might fall right away if you remove a single bit
of wood near them, and perhaps we should not count them in this
category (depending on how exactly we project the metaphor). Likewise
perhaps those which would fall if a small number of easily
identifiable bits of wood were removed. Then, the biframes which
correspond to propositions of this special category – 'Language
exists', 'I have a hand' etc. – are those which don't clearly
depend on any particular bits of wood.
These special biframes are no mere epiphenomena, however: they belong
to our 'frame of reference'.
So in a sense they are foundations:
401.
I want to say: propositions of the form of empirical propositions,
and not only propositions of logic, form the foundation of all
operating with thoughts (with language). ...
But this is then
squared with, for example, the metaphor of biframes, with this
brilliant remark:
248.
I have arrived at the rock bottom of my convictions. And one might
almost say that these foundation-walls are carried by the whole
house.
In
other words: don't be mislead by a “bottom-up” metaphor into
thinking that Moorean propositions are not
themselves supported, in a diffuse way, by non-Moorean empirical
propositions. The image of the cluster of metal frames (or
Wittgenstein's 'nest') helps avoid this: we do not imagine the
cluster extending high into the air, but rather getting denser and
covering a wider area.
And what's the
difference between these and what we call a priori
propositions? In our frame metaphor, the correlates of a priori
propositions – triframes – stand by construction. Here is
what Wittgenstein says about the difference:
655.
The mathematical proposition has, as it were officially, been given
the stamp of incontestability. I. e.: "Dispute about other
things; this is immovable - it is a hinge on which your dispute can
turn."
656. And one can not say that of the proposition that I am called L. W. Nor of the proposition that such-and-such people have calculated such-and-such a problem correctly.
656. And one can not say that of the proposition that I am called L. W. Nor of the proposition that such-and-such people have calculated such-and-such a problem correctly.
657.
The propositions of mathematics might be said to be fossilized. - The
proposition "I am called...." is not. …
Putting this
'fossilization' talk from On Certainty together with the bits
of wood from the metal frame metaphor above, we might say: bits of
wood supporting biframes can petrify and become part of the frames
themselves. (But that is not a plausible story about the actual
origin of each a priori proposition taken individually.
Perhaps it is plausible, however, that when we enter new regions of
the a priori, so to speak, we often do so in this way. Or
that, when humankind apprehended a priori propositions
initially, we got there in this way. But this is all by the by.)
But in this case,
fresh wood may still grow in the same area. And this sheds
light on a distinct metaphor from Wittgenstein's Remarks on the
Foundations of Mathematics which helped inspire the one about
metal frames above: A mathematical proposition stands on four feet;
it is over-determined.
This isn't the same
metaphor, but I wager that these four feet do not all correspond to
the same sort of thing: one of them can be distinguished as the
'fresh wood' alluded to above: for example, nothing can refute '7 + 5
= 12', it is not held hostage to experience (as we can see from the
standard, convincing critiques of Mill's view that arithmetical
propositions are empirical generalizations), and yet!: experience
bears it out in some sense. We put seven and five things
together, and we usually find we have twelve. Or better: our
experience is such that this proposition is useful, is possible even
(i.e. is something we can grasp, use, instantiate).
Another Angle on the Difference
Between Moorean and A
Priori Propositions
Another angle from
which to see the difference between Moorean propositions and a
priori propositions, in particular 'I exist' as we construed it
in the previous section, is with a thought experiment involving
experiences radically different from those most of us have had.
Suppose everything went black and all bodily (kinaesthetic) sensation
ceased, and a voice, claiming to be a demon, or some kind of
scientist, but not belonging to the world of our experience,
announced that space, or everything in it, has been destroyed, so
that there is no language (construed as spatiotemporal occurrences)
and no uttering (construed likewise).
If this happened to
me, I would be unable to refute this. Or at least, no immediate
knock-down objection would come to mind; the most near-to-hand
strategy for refuting it would probably involve appeal to a belief in
psycho-physical parallelism, which the demon would gainsay. I
wouldn't know what to think.
If, on the other
hand, the voice told me that I no longer exist, it would be totally
different: I would steadfastly deny that, and nothing the demon could
say to me would shake my belief that I exist. We will come back to
this in a moment, when we consider how the conceptions of internality
of truth-value and non-Twin-Earthability line up with the traditional
conception of a priority.
To summarize our
conclusions so far:
'I exist' is a
priori (i.e. has its truth-value internally) and
non-Twin-Earthable.
'Language exists'
and 'I am uttering' are a posteriori and non-Twin-Earthable.
This is when we
construe 'I' as not implying the existence of a body, and 'language'
and 'uttering' as meaning spatiotemporal phenomena. If we construe
'I' bodily, 'I exist' falls in line with the other two. Conversely,
if we construe 'language' and 'uttering' as not necessarily being
spatiotemporal, 'Language exists' and 'I am uttering now' may be
argued to fall in line with 'I exist'.
So, we appear to
have two different notions here, with different extensions, both of
which can be legitimate parts of our typology of propositions:
internality of truth-value, and non-Twin-Earthability. We shall
continue to reserve the term 'a priori' for the notion of
internality of truth value. All a priori propositions are
non-Twin-Earthable, but not the other way around.
Are All Non-Twin-Earthable A
Posteriori Propositions Moorean?
The above discussion of propositions which are non-Twin-Earthable yet
a posteriori focused on Moorean propositions – propositions
it is hard or impossible to doubt, and which play a peculiar logical
role in our thought and language which Wittgenstein tried to describe
in On Certainty – such as 'Language exists' and 'I am
uttering now'. Their being like that makes it important to
distinguish them from a priori propositions, since our traffic
with them resembles our traffic with certain a priori propositions
in striking ways: we don't have to look out into the world of
experience to verify them.
The question now arises: are all the propositions which are
non-Twin-Earthable yet a posteriori like that? That is, are
they all Moorean?
The answer, and this seems quite definite, is no: take, for example,
the conjunction 'Language exists and first-order logic is
undecidable'. Adding the second conjunct leaves non-Twin-Earthability
unaffected, since it is a priori, but destroys Mooreanness.
(Or, if you think it's Moorean that first-order logic is undecidable,
pick some less basic a priori fact from the formal sciences.)
Comparison with the Traditional
Conception
How do these two
notions – non-Twin-Earthability, and determination of truth-value
by internal meaning alone (which latter is what we have been
using 'apriority'/'a priori' for), line up with the
traditional conception of a priori truths as those which can
be known without recourse to experience?
Our choice of
terminology above has probably given the game away: the a priori
propositions (those whose truth-values are internal to them) just are
those whose truth-values can be known a priori in the
traditional sense, i.e. without recourse to experience. And, since
the non-Twin-Earthable propositions outrun those whose truth-values
are internal to them (the a priori propositions, on our
usage), they also outrun the propositions which are traditionally a
priori.
I will not embark
on an extensive discussion of the traditional idea, but will be quite
rough and ready with it.
To repeat:
non-Twin-Earthable propositions are not all traditionally-apriori,
but the a priori (on our usage) propositions just are
the traditionally-a priori ones. I regard the first part of
that suggestion as more certain, and more robust with respect to
different precisifications of traditional-apriority, than the second;
.
The
non-Twin-Earthable propositions which are not traditionally-apriori
are the 'transcendent' ones: those whose concrete instantiation
ensures their truth: as we just saw, these include both Moorean
propositions such as 'Language exists' and 'I am uttering now', but
also more complicated, non-obvious transcendental propositions. They
give information concerning what goes on in space and time, and no
propositions traditionally regarded a priori do that (perhaps
an exception must be made for the most extreme Liebnizian
rationalism, but even he distinguished between truths grounded by the
principle of non-contradiction and those grounded by the principle of
sufficient reason).
The case
of 'I am uttering now' seems particularly clear: when we know that,
we are clearly relying on experience: in the most straightforward
case, the very experience of uttering. It could conceivably fail to
come off.
A more
complicated case could be imagined where some antecedent condition is
empirically and reliably connected with me uttering 'I am uttering
now', I might observe the condition and be said to know the
proposition already, i.e. not by means of my experience of uttering
it.
But hold
on: is that right? It might be thought that there is a mistake here,
similar to the mistake that would be made by saying that the way we
know our own intentions is by observation and empirical correlation
(cf. Wittgenstein's
Remarks on the Philosophy of Psychology). We may just know
that we intend to utter, not by observing ourselves, and know that
our intention will be carried out, and then utter 'I am uttering now'
knowingly. But in that case we may say: very well, but you are still
drawing on past experience in knowing that your intention will be
carried out. Furthermore, we can maintain high standards of knowledge
and say: you don't really know you're uttering now until you
experience it (hear it, see it, feel it etc.), because something
could go wrong with your attempt at uttering – your larynx could
disappear, for example.
So, not
all non-Twin-Earthable propositions are traditionally a priori:
'I am uttering now' is the former but not the latter.
Does the
converse hold? Are all traditionally a priori propositions
non-Twin-Earthable? I say Yes, but I will not bother arguing this
directly, since it falls out from the other things I am arguing: that
the a priori propositions are just the traditionally a
priori propositions, and all a
priori propositions
are non-Twin-Earthable.
One
challenge to the idea that the a priori propositions – i.e.
those whose truth-values are determined by their internal meanings
alone – just are the traditionally a priori propositions is
that already troublesome proposition, 'I exist'. Above, we made a
case for saying that – provided the 'I' is construed in such as way
as not to require the existence of a body – this proposition is a
priori: its internal meaning determines its truth-value. And our
intuitive considerations in favour of that were not unrelated to the
traditional conception of apriority: we spoke of 'looking out into
the world', 'looking into the language-system', and reasoning.
I think
we should follow through with this, and say that 'I exist' (on our
“bodiless” construal of it) is traditionally a priori: you
can know it without recourse to experience.
However,
there is an opposing line of thought here. We see it, for example, in
Chalmers. Chalmers' idea about 'I exist' is that we know it via
introspection, which is a kind of experience. But we may want a
narrower concept of experience which this doesn't fall under.
It
is admitted by Chalmers that it is 'somewhat controversial' that 'I
exists' can only be known on the basis of experience. 'I am uttering
now', on the other hand, Chalmers regards as a clear case of
something that can only be known the basis of experience.
I
propose to go along with this, and say that 'Language exists' and 'I
am uttering now', construed so that they give information about
spatiotemporal goings-on, is neither traditionally a priori
nor a priori in our
internality sense.
It
is clear that 'Language exists' and 'I am uttering now', construed
the way they are supposed to be construed, give information about
particular contents of space and time – and that makes us feel that
in some sense, surely, these can only be known on the basis of
experience. But it seems there is a conceptual gap between 'I exist'
and 'I occupy space and time' (or anything else which says something
about the contents of space and time) – otherwise Descartes'
recovery of his old beliefs would have been considerably easier.
(Here we come upon
an interesting difference between space and time. Kant's calling time
'the form of the internal sense' and space 'the form of the external
sense' is suggestive of it, so perhaps he comments on it somewhere.
Roughly: while perhaps I could be taken out of the “time-space” I
was in and put into another one, so that there is no fact about
whether I am presently earlier or later than my birth in external
time (in the sense of Lewis's distinction between personal and
external time), but I cannot imagine not being in any time-space
at all. If everything went dark and all bodily sensation ceased, and
I heard a voice telling me I have been taken out of space, I would be
unable to refute this. Or at least, no immediate knock-down objection
would come to mind; the most near-to-hand strategy for refuting it
would probably involve appeal to a belief in psycho-physical
parallelism, which could only be founded on experience. If the voice,
on the other hand, told me I had been deprived of all temporal
locatedness and relations, I would immediately be able to see that
this was in some important sense wrong. We might say that spatial
locatedness is a posteriori, temporal locatedness (in some
sense, at least – i.e. Lewis's personal time) a priori.)
Another major
source of potential difficulty for my thesis that the traditionally
a priori propositions just are the a priori ones in our
internality sense, perhaps the most fundamental source of difficulty,
is the synthetic a priori; substantial a priori truths
which don't seem to be “true in virtue of meaning” in the sense
that 'A priori propositions are those whose truth-values are
internal to them', for example, is in this discussion (since we
stipulated that we would use 'a priori' for internality of
truth-value).
To begin to meet
this difficulty, we must give an account of the analytic-synthetic
distinction. I will make a start on this in the next post.