The Humphrey
objection to modal realism, due to Kripke, centres on counterpart theory, and alleges
that this assigns counterintuitive truth-conditions to modal
statements about individuals. It is historically important, as Kripke
made the objection in his influential Naming and Necessity
lectures, long before Lewis published his full defence of modal
realism in 1986.
Kripke
put the objection as follows:
Thus
if we say "Humphrey might have won the election (if only he had
done such-and-such)”, we are not talking about something that might
have happened to Humphrey
but
to someone else, a "counterpart". Probably, however,
Humphrey could not care less whether someone else,
no matter how much resembling him, would have been victorious in
another possible world. Thus, Lewis's view seems to me even more
bizarre than the usual notions of transworld identification that it
replaces. (Kripke 1980:45 note 13.)
It is by now, I
think, pretty widely accepted that Kripke, while he may have been on
to something here, did not put the point optimally. To the objection
put this way, there is a cogent response: it is not correct to say
that, according to counterpart-theoretic modal realism, we 'are not
talking about something that might have happened to Humphrey'.
What counterpart-theoretic says is that talk about 'what might have
happened to Humphrey' is to be analyzed in terms of what does
happen to his counterparts in other worlds. So according to the
counterpart-theoretic modal realist, when we say 'Humphrey might have
won the election', we are indeed talking about what might have
happened to Humphrey. Their characteristic claim is to add that this
thing we're talking about is to be analyzed in terms of what happens
to counterparts. (Lewis drives this point home in On the Plurality of Worlds.)
Similarly, the
second part of Kripke's objection – that 'Humphrey could not care
less whether someone else, no matter how much resembling him,
would have been victorious in another possible world' – can be
convincingly argued to miss the mark. The counterpart-theoretic modal
realist can agree that Humphrey could not care less about this. For
the way they analyze talk about whether 'someone else' (a
counterpart) 'would have been victorious in another possible world'
is in terms of counterparts of that someone else – counterparts of
Humphrey's counterparts. And it is compatible with Humphrey not being
interested in what happens to the counterparts of some one of his
counterparts, that he be interested in something which – upon
analysis – turns out to be a question of what happens to his own
counterparts.
This last point may
be a bit pedantic, however. What if we simply reform the second part
of Kripke's objection by changing the 'would have been' to an 'is'?
This yields: 'Humphrey could not care less whether someone else,
no matter how much resembling him, is victorious in another possible
world?'
This is better, but
there is still a strong reply. As Sider says in his unpublished
'Beyond the Humphrey Objection', this is 'just the paradox of
analysis':
A reasonable
person can care about a property under one description (“possibly
winning”) while not caring about the same property under another
description (“having a counterpart who wins”), provided it is not
obvious that the descriptions pick out the same property. Correct
analyses need not be obvious to competent language users. Obviousness
may count for something, but theoretical virtues are important as
well in determining which analyses we ought to accept (p. 2)
I endorse this as a
response to the version of the Humphrey objection just considered.
However, I want presently to register a difference with Sider
about whether this response also works for another version of the
objection.
This other version
puts aside what Humphrey cares about, and appeals directly to our
intuitions. Sider puts this version of the objection as follows:
'Look, it is just obvious that possibly winning is not the
same as having a counterpart who wins' (pp. 1 – 2) And the response
quoted above is put forward by Sider as a response to both the
previously considered version and this one. (He explicitly prefaces
the passage with 'Reply to ii) and iii)' (p. 2).)
Does Sider's
response apply here too? On reflection, I think clearly not. The
response makes the point that a correct analysis need not be obvious
(while granting that obviousness may count for something). But the
present version of the objection is alleging, not that it isn't
obvious, but that it is obviously not the case. Sider, in putting the
passage in question forward as a response to this, is sliding
from '(~p) is obvious' to '~(p is obvious)' and thus
failing to address the objection.
So we seem to have
a version of the Humphrey objection which is stronger than the others
so far considered. But we can improve it further by getting away from
obviousness altogether, which is a red herring. Saying that possibly
winning is obviously not the same as having a winning
counterpart risks being too strong. The rhetorically wise thing to do
is tone it down, and simply enter a plea that it doesn't intuitively
seem that possibly winning is the same as having a winning
counterpart. Or putting the point semantically: the truth-condition
Lewis assigns to 'Humphrey could have won' is counterintuitive.
So, despite the
availability of strong responses to the original and certain
subsequent versions of the Humphrey objection, the core point remains
that the truth-condition assigned by Lewis is counterintuitive.
(Incidentally,
Lewis suggested that forms of ersatzism are no better on this score:
in that case, what “gets into the act” is not another person, but
'some abstract whatnot' (Lewis 1986, p. 194.) This isn't a strong
reply to the objection, of course, as ersatzism is far from the only
other game in town when it comes to the semantics of modal
attributions such as 'Humphrey might have won'. Nevertheless and for
what it's worth: perhaps an abstract whatnot getting into the act is,
from an intuitive point of view, not quite as bad as another person
getting into the act. Bringing in another person, it seems to me,
feels more like crowding out Humphrey, more like putting something in
his place.)
So, there is a
version of the Humphrey objection which has some force. However,
modal realism with overlap, in contrast to counterpart-theoretic
modal realism a la Lewis, is immune to the Humphrey objection.
Lewis wasn't swayed by this, since he had reasons to think modal
realism with overlap unpalatable. Since then, advocates of overlap
have, as might have been predicted, emerged (most notably McDaniel in his (2004), 'Modal Realism with Overlap').
It may be that the
considerations against overlap are quite compelling, in which case
these together with the Humphrey objection (once it is freed from its
initial faulty formulation) have significant force against modal
realism in general. However, I do not want to get deep into comparing
the relative merits of counterpart-theoretic modal realism and modal
realism with overlap, and would prefer to have an objection along
similar lines which applies to both. Therefore, I advocate that we
take the Humphrey objection, not just as a self-sufficient objection
which affects the dominant form of modal realism but not modal
realism with overlap, but also as a clue: modal realism – in both
flavours – may be counterintuitive on the semantic front, and this
may be a good reason to reject it. Since the Humphrey objection
itself fails to apply to modal realism with overlap, we should set it
aside and go on to try for a more general semantic objection. I hope to develop this in a future post.
References
Kripke, Saul A. (1980). Naming and Necessity. Harvard University Press.
Lewis, David K. (1986). On the Plurality of Worlds. Blackwell Publishers.
McDaniel, Kris (2004). Modal realism with overlap. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 82 (1):137 – 152.
Sider, Theodore. unpublished. Beyond the Humphrey Objection.