Here I want to suggest one reason why people have had trouble seeing a middle way between descriptivism and Millianism about names - that is, why my sort of view of names has not already prevailed or at least become a prominent option. (It is far from the only reason, and I will consider others in future posts.) This may also afford us some insight into why both descriptivists and Millians endorse their respective views.
The articulation assumption is that, if you say that names have meanings beyond their referents, you have to be able, at least in principle, to specify what they are, and in some way which articulates or unpacks these meanings. The assumption is at work in B's role in this short dialogue:
A: Names have meanings over and above their bearers.
B: What's the meaning of 'John Nash', then?
I am envisaging B's reply here as a Millian-leaning attempt to embarrass A out of their assertion.
And what I want to say here is that A need not have anything to reply here, in order to have respectably made their assertion.
To see this, it helps to reflect that, in saying 'what the meaning of' an expression is, what we are doing is giving, or at least referring to, an expression which has the same meaning as the one whose meaning is in question. And there is no reason why a name like 'John Nash' needs to be synonymous with any other expression, let alone one with more structure (so that it could be said to articulate or unpack the meaning of 'John Nash').
One of the functions of semantic notions is to bundle and separate
instances of expressions. We bundle by ascribing the same meaning, we
separate by ascribing different meanings.
Frege, who notoriously says precious little about his senses, at one point says that the sense of 'Aristotle' might be: the teacher of Alexander. (I reproduce his style of formulation, using a colon and no quote marks, but I don't mean to say this is clear and unambiguous.) But we don't need to do any such thing.
Making the articulation assumption could be one of the forces pushing thinkers who are impressed by anti-descriptivist arguments, such as Kripke's, toward Millianism. Likewise, it could be one of the forces pushing thinkers who are impressed by anti-Millian considerations, such as the apparent difference in meaning between 'Hesperus is Hesperus' and 'Hesperus is Phosphorus' and the apparent meaningfulness true singular negative existentials like 'Santa doesn't exist', toward (perhaps sophisticated) forms of descriptivism.
Once you reflect that the articulation assumption is false, it becomes clear that there is a middle way, quite immune to both sets of problems.
Tuesday, 17 June 2014
Tuesday, 3 June 2014
Worrying about Facts
This is the last in a series of posts on facts (the four links are to the earlier members).
There is an inchoate kind of worry about facts which,
while closely related to projection-based skepticism (discussed in the last post), is not
automatically discredited once we discredit projection-based
skepticism. One way of expressing it would be to say that facts –
or certain classes of facts, perhaps – seem like shadowy or queer
entities. I will try to say something about what is going on here,
but it is a large and profound theme which affects a lot of
philosophy, so what I say here can do little more than scratch the
surface and indicate a broad sort of viewpoint. The line I take on this is broadly Wittgensteinian.
Such an inchoate
worry seems to animate the following remarks of Russell's in the
Atomism lectures:
I
do not suppose there is in the world a single
disjunctive fact corresponding to “p or q”. It does
not look plausible that in the actual objective world there are facts
going about which you could describe as “p or q”,
but I would not lay too much stress on what strikes one as plausible:
it is not a thing you can rely on altogether. For the present I do
not think any difficulties will arise from the supposition that the
truth or falsehood of this proposition “p or q”
does not depend upon a single objective fact which is disjunctive but
depends on the two facts one of which corresponds to p and the
other to q: p will have a fact corresponding to it and
q will have a fact corresponding to it.
And
a bit later:
One has a certain
repugnance to negative facts, the same sort of feeling that makes you
wish not to have a fact “p or q” going about the
world. You have a feeling that there are only positive facts, and
that negative propositions have somehow or other got to be
expressions of positive facts. When I was lecturing on this subject
at Harvard4 I argued that there were negative facts, and it nearly
produced a riot: the class would not hear of there being negative
facts at all. I am still inclined to think that there are. However,
one of the men to whom I was lecturing at Harvard, Mr. Demos,
subsequently wrote an article in Mind to explain why there are
no negative facts. It is in Mind for April 1917. I think he
makes as good a case as can be made for the view that there are no
negative facts. It is a difficult question. I really only ask that
you should not dogmatize. I do not say positively that there are, but
there may be.
There is obviously
something weird about this way of talking. It has a certain charm,
even, for some – I confess even I find it charming and not just
strange. The same holds for much of the Atomism lectures.
Nevertheless, I think we need to get beyond this sort of talk, and
submit it to philosophical scrutiny. Wittgenstein has done more
toward this than anyone else I know of.
It was certain sorts
of facts Russell was worried about above – negative and disjunctive
facts. But other considerations, such as our considerations above
about concepts or modes of presentations getting into the
individuation of facts, and granularity considerations'
applying to facts, may give rise to similar worries about positive,
atomic facts. Others, like Quine, Strawson, and perhaps William
James, have been more generally worried about facts.
Also, similar
shadowiness and queerness worries come up in other areas: thoughts,
meanings, sensations, and mathematical objects. And then there are
cases where the very things which worry these worriers are seized
upon and embraced, e.g. mystical Pythagoreanism and Platonism.
One of the
fundamental things going wrong in these worries, I believe, is that
the worriers are making the mistake of passing over the question of
sense, and going straight for the question of truth. A similar thing
occurs when writers opposed to Platonism about mathematical objects
go all autobiographical and tell us that they find the view 'wildly
implausible' or the like.
In
both sorts of cases – incredulity about facts, or particular sorts
of facts, and incredulity about the mind-independent existence of
mathematical objects – the worriers are onto something, some
problem in their way of looking at things, and perhaps that of others
(such as quasi-mysterian metaphysicians embracing facts and numbers
with a lot of hocus pocus). But they mistakenly read it into the
forms of expression which gave rise to their misunderstandings –
forms which in themselves are not guilty. They then make the mistake
of, instead of clarifying how these forms really work, what they
really mean, casting doubt on the truth
of
what they may be used to say.
This
is very clear in Russell's remarks above. ('I would not lay too much
stress on what strikes one as plausible: it is not a thing you can
rely on altogether', 'I really only ask that you should
not dogmatize. I do not say positively
that there are, but there may be.' All of this suggests a difficult
factual question - none of it suggests any difficulty with our
understanding of what we are saying.)
What I am saying
here is reminiscent of the following remarks of Wittgenstein's:
PI: 194. When
we do philosophy we are like savages, primitive people, who hear the
expressions of civilized men, put a false interpretation on them, and
then draw the queerest conclusions from it. (PI.)
Zettel: 450.
One who philosophizes often makes the wrong, inappropriate gesture
for a verbal expression.
451.
(One says the ordinary thing—with the wrong gesture.)
This idea of 'saying
the ordinary thing with the wrong gesture' gives us a way of thinking
about what is going on when the mysterian metaphysician and the
worried doubter alike use the forms which give rise to these worries.
Russell's colourful
talk of facts 'going about' in 'the actual, objective world' as it
were expresses just such a wrong gesture, putting cues for it into
the words themselves, so that the words themselves become more
inherently misleading.
The
treatment I suggest for these residual worries about facts, then, is
the same sort of treatment instanced in this passage in the
Investigations
(where
the topic is not fact-talk, but our inclination to say that, when we
have grasped the meaning of an expression, its use is then 'present',
or 'determined'):
195.
“But I don't mean that what I do now (in grasping a sense)
determines the future use causally
and
as a matter of experience, but that in a queer
way, the use itself is in some sense present.”--But of course it
is, “in some
sense”! Really the only thing wrong with what you say is the
expression “in a queer way”. The rest is all right; and the
sentence only seems queer when one imagines a different language-game
for it from the one in which we actually use it. (Someone once told
me that as a child he had been surprised that a tailor could 'sew a
dress'--he thought this meant that a dress was produced by sewing
alone, by sewing one thread onto another.)
When we fail to look
sufficiently closely, in a sufficiently unprejudiced way, at the way
fact-talk works, we assimilate its working with that of other talk we
know, and it looks funny to us. We sometimes react by doubting that
there really are facts, or that there really are certain kinds of
facts. But we may also react with an overly thin and superficial
deflationism, which doesn't do sufficient justice to the real office
of fact-talk.
References
Bertrand Russell (1985). The Philosophy of Logical Atomism. Open Court.
Ludwig Wittgenstein (2003). Philosophical Investigations: The German Text, with a Revised English Translation. Blackwell.
Ludwig Wittgenstein (1967). Zettel. Oxford, Blackwell.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)