This is a draft of a paper.
Alan Sidelle's conventionalism about
modality is well-known, and only a bit less of a
whipping-boy than the earlier positivistic views of Ayer (1936) and
Carnap (1947). Published in his 1989 book Necessity, Essence and
Individuation: A Defense of Conventionalism,
it focuses on the problem of explaining the existence of the
necessary a posteriori
from a metaphysical standpoint according to which (in Sidelle's
phrase) we, and not the world, are the source of modality. (I think
this isn't very clear, but I don't want to press that here.)
I will
not give a proper exposition of Sidelle's account here. I will just say that the basic idea is that a modal claim such as
'Necessarily, water is H20' follows from the a posteriori
claim 'Water is H20' together with an a priori
claim, such as 'If water is H20, then necessarily, water is H20'. The
idea is that the a priori
claim is somehow a matter of convention.
There
are many problems with such a view – see Yablo's incisive (1992)
review for a start. For example, can
the a priori claim
really be said to be a matter of convention? How doesn't this fall
prey to the following argument?: it may be that what sentences mean is
conventional, but we can't make the propositions they mean true by
convention, except for the special case of propositions about
conventions. (Yablo calls this the Lewy point, citing Lewy (1976). See
also Quine (1936).) And even if this is somehow surmounted, aren't we
still in the dark about what necessity is?
(While Sidelle's aims, when stated carefully, do not seem to include
saying what necessity is, some of his more impressionistic rhetoric
does seem to try to say something about that. In any case, his
account leaving us in the dark about the nature of necessity, if it
does, is something worth taking due note of, since it is commonly taken to be addressing that issue.)
Here I
will discuss another central objection (or type of objection) –
that from the contingency of conventions. Or rather, Sidelle's
recent response to it; in a 2009 paper called 'Conventionalism and
the Contingency of Conventions', Sidelle defends his conventionlism
about modality from this sort of objection.
He carefully distinguishes two objections here, one focusing on
truth-making, the other on necessity-making:
Truth-making
version. If conventions were different, certain necessary truths
would not be true. This seems to follow from conventionalism,
catching it in a contradiction – since what it is to be a
necessary truth is not failing to be true in any circumstances.
Necessity-making
version. If conventions were different, certain necessary truths may
have been contingent. This seems to follow from conventionalism, but
seems wrong.
Sidelle
argues (convincingly, in my view) that (1) is wrong – the
conventionalist isn't committed to that. (I refer readers to his
paper for this.)
Sidelle
acknowledges (2) to be more serious, and devotes his paper to
responding to it. Here, I will argue that his response to (2) fails
at an early step, for use-mention reasons.
Sidelle
considers but rejects one possible avenue of response, a partly
bullet-biting response which says: OK, so this shows that, at least
sometimes, what is necessarily so may not have been necessarily so
(and also that, at least sometimes, what is contingently so may not
have been contingently so). Such truths, then, are contingently
necessary and contingently contingent, respectively. This is
tantamount to rejecting the characteristic axiom of S4 – that what
is necessary is necessarily necessary.
Sidelle
will not have this. It is simply too implausible that the S4 axiom
fails for metaphysical modality. Indeed, there is reason to think
that the appropriate system is S5 (since an unrestricted
accessibility relation seems appropriate), which is stronger than S4.
Furthermore, he says, conventionalists, in his opinion, ought to try
to “save the modal phenomena” and not be highly revisionary.
He
also has an argument to the effect that even biting this bullet
wouldn't suffice, but I do not understand that argument (I think
because it involves certain confusions bound up with Sidelle's form
of conventionalism, but I won't try to go into that here).
Sidelle's
strategy with (2) is to consider an example – that of 'bachelor',
and what would be the case if our conventions governing it were
different – and try to show that, if we are careful to stick to the
proper mode of evaluating counterfactuals, namely where we keep our
conventions, and the meanings of
our terms, intact, we can see that the relevant (2)-like counterfactuals are not
true.
Sidelle
supposes for the sake of argument that our conventions make it that
'bachelor' applies to unmarried but eligible men, and not women, and
then considers an alternative situation in which the conventions
differed so that unmarried, eligible women fell in the extension of
'bachelor':
With
such a convention, we would call unmarried Linda ‘a bachelor’,
and so,
‘necessarily, bachelors are male’ would be false. However, how
should we
describe
this situation? Is Linda a female bachelor? Of course not—someone
counts as a bachelor only if they are male. Our rules for applying
‘bachelor’ tell us that one must be (give or take) ‘a
never-been-married, but eligible male’ [footnote 14]—so
ipso
facto,
the rules tell us that what rules the speakers in
that
world use is quite irrelevant to whether or not someone is a
bachelor. They are no more relevant than the rules of Spanish if we
are, in English, describing a situation in Mexico. And of course,
this is perfectly general. Notice that this has nothing at
all to do
with Conventionalism—it
is what anyone should believe about evaluating counterfactuals, when
those counterfactuals contain words governed by certain semantic
conventions—and of course, one doesn’t need to be a
Conventionalist to believe there are at least some, or even many,
such conventions. [footnote 15]
And as the
conventions in that situation are irrelevant to the truth of ‘Linda
is a female bachelor’, so are they to the question of the necessity
of
bachelors’ being male there, and so, to whether our necessary
truth is itself necessarily so (i.e. to whether or not it is
necessarily necessary that
bachelors are male). Thus, if
the
conventionalist story is correct, it will not
be true
that ‘had our conventions been different, what is necessary would
(could) have been false’, or not necessary.
The
first part of this quote is an unexceptionable rehearsal of how to
evaluate counterfactuals dealing with situations where the meanings
of words differ: don't get confused into using
the words with those different meanings in describing the situation:
it isn't the case that, if 'tail' meant 'leg', dogs would have four
tails – although 'Dogs have four tails' would be true in such a
situation, ceteris paribus.
So while 'Dogs have four tails' would, in that situation, say
something true, it does not actually say something true of that
situation, i.e. about what happens in that situation.
Similarly
with the sentence 'Linda is a female bachelor' – it would say
something true in the
situation in question, but it isn't – given what it actually means
– actually true of
that situation.
So
far, so good. The trouble is in the last two sentences, when Sidelle
tries to conclude from his unexceptionable rehearsal that it's not
the case that, if our conventions were different, which propositions
are necessary might be different. The last sentence just gives the
conclusion. The whole argument, really, is in the second last
sentence, so we will concentrate on that. Here it is again, with two
words capitalized by me:
And
as the conventions in that situation are irrelevant to the truth of
‘Linda is a female bachelor’, so are they to the question of the
necessity
of
bachelors’ being male there, AND SO, to whether our necessary truth
is itself necessarily so (i.e. to whether or not it is necessarily
necessary that bachelors are male).
Firstly,
there is an ambiguity in Sidelle's phrase 'the truth of “Linda is a
female bachelor”'. The conventions in that situation are obviously
not irrelevant to the truth, in that situation, of the sentence
'Linda is a female bachelor'. But it is true that they are irrelevant
to whether or not that sentence is actually true of the
situation: it isn't of course, because there can't be female
bachelors in any
possible situation. So we can accept this and move on to see what
Sidelle is likening it to.
The
way Sidelle has put the point, it is not easy to see what the
similarity is. The conventions in that situation are irrelevant to
the truth of some sentence here,
and similarly, to the necessity of bachelors being male there?
The points would seem more similar if Sidelle semantically descended
for the first bit: just as the conventions in that situation are
irrelevant to whether Linda is a female bachelor in that
situation, so too are they
irrelevant to whether the bachelors are necessarily male there.
In any
case, the point can be accepted: bachelors are necessarily male, in
all situations. So in a situation where the conventions were
different, any bachelors would still need to be male.
But,
and this is the crucial point, in saying this, we are using our
language, with our conventions, and describing a counterfactual
scenario. Our proposition 'Necessarily, all the bachelors are male'
is true of that situation.
Call the situation S – our more explicit proposition 'Necessarily,
all the bachelors are male in S' is true. And you can substitute for
'S' the name of any possible situation.
To ask
of that situation, of S, whether the bachelors are necessarily male
there, is palpably not
to ask whether the proposition that bachelors are male – the
proposition now, or whatever thing bears modal statuses, not just the
sentence – is necessarily true in that situation.
That question just hasn't been raised.
And
this is why 'AND SO' is capitalized – it is spurious. It just
doesn't follow from all the bachelors in situation S necessarily
being male – that's us describing the scenario from here, remember
– that the proposition that bachelors are male is necessarily true
in that situation –
and so you can't conclude from it that some proposition of ours which
is necessarily true is necessarily necessarily true. Of course, such
a conclusion is itself plausible, but that doesn't mean Sidelle
– a conventionalist about the modal statuses of propositions – is
entitled to it! And his argument only gets there by means of a
subtle, illicit use-mention shift.
Having
established to his satisfaction that he is not committed to what is
necessary varying with convention, Sidelle then faces the task of
explaining why the following plausible constraint on explanation
fails in this instance: if A explains B, it can't be that no change
in B would ever come about if A changed.
I
think there are serious problems with his attempt, and I hope to make
this clear in future. My purpose here has just been to show that the
previous step, which led Sidelle to having to face this question
about explanation, is fallacious. Sidelle has slid from mention to use in the consequents of the counter-conventional,
counterfactual conditionals at issue: he can agree with everyone else
that, if conventions had been different, any bachelors would still
necessarily be male, but this is not the same as being able to agree
that, if conventions had been different, the proposition that any
bachelors are male would still be necessary. His argument from common
knowledge about how to evaluate counterfactuals does not succeed in
earning him the right to the latter, only the former. We can conclude
from this alone that Sidelle has not adequately responded to the
(necessity-making focused) objection from the contingency of
conventions.
References
Ayer, A.J. (1936). Language, Truth
and Logic. London, V. Gollancz, Ltd.
Carnap, Rudolf (1947). Meaning and
Necessity. University of Chicago Press.
Lewy, Casimir (1976). Meaning and
Modality. Cambridge University Press.
Quine, W.V. (1936). Truth by Convention. In The Ways of Paradox and Other Essays.
Sidelle, Alan (2009). Conventionalism
and the contingency of conventions. Noûs 43 (2):224-241.
Sidelle,
Alan (1989). Necessity, Essence, and Individuation: A
Defense of Conventionalism.
Cornell University Press.
Yablo, Stephen (1992). "Review of
Alan Sidelle, Necessity, Essence and Individuation."
Philosophical Review 101: 878-81.